There are a number of figures ostensibly operating in a similar political space as many of us posting on this platform. One such example is Andrew Doyle. I do largely enjoy his commentary and find him to be engaging. However, I do not agree with his assessment of Liberlism. Chiefly demonstrated in this interview: https://youtu.be/V9LebwsT4TU?feature=shared
This has prompted me to begin to formulate a somewhat accessible critique of Andrew’s position on Liberalism. I would appreciate your feedback:
Liberalism aspires to be a universal ideal, a solution for all societies. Yet, its efficacy is anchored in the Western context, which serves as its substrate.
Core principles—rule of law, equality before the law, individual liberty, and equal rights—derive their meaning and success from this substrate. But what do these principles entail? Rights to what end? The right to mistreat animals—is that defensible if universally applied? What of laws? A law banning property ownership or prohibiting sneezing on Tuesdays—would these be acceptable if enforced equally? And individual liberty—what defines it? Is any form justifiable so long as it is universal? As long as it’s democratic?
Liberalism flourishes in the West because of its substrate: a foundation of Christian values, time-honoured institutions, and personal liberties shaped over centuries. Yet, when exported to other substrates—societies with divergent histories, values, and structures—it often fails. The West’s attempts to impose liberalism, from post-colonial state-building in Africa to interventions in the Middle East, have frequently led to instability or rejection. Why?
Liberalism acts as a doping agent, enhancing the potential of a specific substrate. In our case, that substrate is the West’s unique cultural and historical framework. Without this foundation, liberalism falters, unable to take root. My contention is that we must prioritise safeguarding this substrate first, then we can once again consider the application of liberalism’s doping agent. The doping agent alone, without a compatible substrate, is ineffective.
Language studies reveal how profoundly thought is shaped by available words—a subtle difference with significant impact. Now consider substrates vastly different from ours, where disparities in language, culture, and history compound exponentially. Societies are not equal because they are not identical. Some substrates can be effectively enhanced by liberalism’s doping agent; others resist or destabilise under its influence.
Therefore, liberalism isn’t a value system itself; it’s an augmentation of a value system, an additional layer. It’s a lens, not the light itself, focusing the West’s cultural radiance but powerless without it. The more the substrate degrades, the less predictable and desirable the doping agent’s effect on it is, dimming the light and rendering the lens ineffective. This is what we now witness: as the Western substrate degrades, yet still doped with liberalism, it yields warped, unsettling, and sometimes immoral outcomes—a distorted pattern of light through a liberal lens.
What, then, degraded the Western substrate? Could the doping agent itself—liberalism in its concentrated form, applied over decades—have corroded it? If doping agents can erode their substrate, what other agent has been applied with such potency as liberalism in the West over the past century?